Thursday, January 10, 2008

The Ethics of Designer Children

Some time ago I happened to record an interview on NPR with Michael Sandel, a Harvard philosopher about the ethics of genetic engineering (he recently published a book The case Against Perfection). It got me thinking, and I thought I might share some ... thoughts.


In the last two decades, our rapidly developing biotechnology has brought us into the realm of human genetic engineering. We are now able to not only screen for many diseases and a few genetic characteristics, but are on the verge of being able to select characteristics of a child. So far this has been limited to the sex of the unborn (for $10-20K), but these will soon expand.

The ethics of this new technology has - as is traditionally been the case – lagged behind the scientific capability. Despite the engagement of prominent intellectuals -- Jurgen Habermas, probably the most important living Continental philosopher wrote a short tract on it a few years ago (The Future of Human Nature), and now so has Michael Sandel -- a truly public debate has not materialized, aside from brief flashes over Dolly the sheep and stem-cell research.

In his discussion, Sandel brings up several fundamental issues: the role and importance of choice as such, the distinction between medical treatment and enhancement, and perfection of species as such. These slippery topics will hopefully make the following discussion more interesting.

Genetic alteration of children remains the locus of the discussion with Sandel, and there are two big points there:

1) in a classically Marxist line, Sandel argues from the point of view of the parents - if they can choose the characteristics of a child they will treat it no different than produce – as a commodity. According to him, such an attitude is simply inappropriate when it comes to children, who, like other relatives (say, parents) should be loved for the relation, not their qualities. As an example of this view taken to the extreme, he points to parents who choose to bring to term a child with Down's syndrome.

But Sandel has to fudge a lot here, blurring together relatively neutral cosmetic characteristics -- hair, eye color -- and 'merit qualities' - (predisposition to) intelligence, musical talent, height, build, etc. While customizing a child like a weekend sports car seems ethically dubious, one can't condemn parents for choosing a smarter or taller than average child on these grounds, for they can reasonably say they are doing it entirely for the child's good. We are assuming fairness does not enter the picture here – that everyone would have equal access to these technologies.

So instead, Sandel is forced to rely here on his distinction between medical treatment and 'enhancement', which distinguishes ensuring a child has higher intellectual potential as reprehensible, while screening for diseases is ok. I will address this distinction below; at this point, we should just note that the moral status of genetic engineering will hinge on this distinction for Sandel.

2) Jurgen Habermas, on the other hand, argues against human genetic engineering because of the effect on the child - the awareness of having been engineered by another person, rather than just fate. Now, rather then a purely philosophical question as he characterizes it, it is in fact an empirical psychological one, similar in nature to the effect of discovering that one is adopted. However, its not a priori clear what effect a revelation of genetic tampering would have, especially in a society where that is fairly commonplace. In fact, not having had good genes arranged in a society where that is common would likely prove even more psychologically damaging. In any case, I'm insisting the question is empirical rather than an abstractly metaphysical.

In contrast to the two philosophers, I would say my position is more practical, which brings me back to Sandel's distinction of medical and enhancement (negative and positive) treatment.

“Treatment vs. Enhancement”

Is there a real (moral) distinction between medical treatment and enhancement? Sandel argues yes – medical treatment restores 'natural human functioning' (for example, growth hormone deficiency resulting in exceptionally short height) while enhancement is more like a consumer good. But how does one define ‘natural human functioning’? The condition of the average human? This widely depends on the environment – what is a 'natural human environment' – savannas? Jungles? Certainly not the living conditions of 99% of contemporary humans.

Ultimately such a distinction can only refer to the below/above average human condition in a given society - from which it is much more difficult to extract a moral argument. What is the significance of this? Well, when it comes to practical policy issues, it's not too great. So, for Sandel, plastic surgery is a 'non-medical consumer good', not a public good like regular medical services, hence they should be treated differently. This may include decreased health insurance coverage, forcing (non-reconstructive) plastic surgeons to repay any federal grants/scholarships they received while in medical school, etc. Overall not particularly controversial, because it addresses a compromiseable, ‘linear’ issue.

Choice

However, if we deny moral weight to the “treatment vs. enhancement” distinction, Sandel is on shakier ground when it comes to parents selecting genes of their children. And this is the case because another moral factor comes in – choice. A reasonable (in America) rejoinder to Sandel is that choice is a fundamental right, of parents among other instances. In the radio program that I refer to, Sandel brilliantly replied that while choice is important, it is not absolute or even a self-standing good (“choice is not an altar we should all worship at”). This is a particularly appropriate response for him, given his communitarian concept of freedom, which emphasizes context and social links over absolute notions and rights like a naked ‘right to choose’.

One problem with allowing such choice for parents is that it inhibits them (and society more generally) from learning to accept things about children – it takes away the ‘gift of human nature’. In this case, according to Sandel, the right to choose would be trumped because, given the enhancement distinction, choice for enhancement is morally lower than choice for medical treatment and doesn't place it above other considerations (those discussed above). But if the distinction doesn’t hold as a sharp line, his reply is no longer valid, especially when we acknowledge the difference between neutral “customization” gene selection -- or something like abortion conditional on genetic quality -- and enhancing the genetic stock of one’s child to improve their potential in life. In that case, it would be difficult to justify restraint on the latter opportunity from the point of view of a single family. Choice is no longer obviously morally less important. So perhaps at this juncture we should widen our scope to consider the policy for society as a whole – i.e. eugenics.

Eugenics

If gene selection is not objectionable for a given parent within society, it implies society as a whole accepts genetic selection of children and its likely outcome (given social pressure) – accelerated genetic drift in a steady direction, i.e. uncoordinated eugenics. What is the problem with making explicit and coordinated? As Sandel notes, we often object to eugenics because it has historically been bound up with coercion, so perhaps there is nothing wrong with it if is voluntary (for the moment treating the choice of a parent considering whether to assure his child high intelligence in a society that discriminates against the unintelligent as still voluntary). But he argues that such a program would be pure hubris – we would presume to know what is best for humanity. We would be playing God. Not to mention (as Sandel does), the danger of ‘inscribing in genes' present prejudices, something bound to happen when genetic engineering is done on a wide scale.

Clearly, organized (or wide-scale) endeavors in human genetic engineering is quite hazardous. There is also the possibility that (international competition aside) there is little to be gained from genetic improvement on a national scale. What do we gain if the US population becomes a little stronger on average, a little taller, or even a little more predisposed to intelligence? “Subjective welfare” studies clearly show that growth of per capita GDP in Western societies does not correspond to growth in subjective well-being. This is in part because many characteristics we hold important are inherently relative – they are “positional goods” (basically, goods whose value derives from factors external to the good itself). Just as the benefits of wealth above some threshold are relative to one’s peers, so would be genetic endowment.

Midway conclusions

Based on the considerations so far, I would argue along with Sandel that programs that encourage genetic enhancement in a particular direction are a bad idea. Private ventures, like a recent attempt to propagate the genes of Nobel laureates, are less censurable largely because of their smaller scale. But when it comes to individual parents and doctors, I would disagree with Sandel. The argument so far shows there is nothing morally wrong with parents selecting their children’s genes as such, at least when it would not reasonably seem to be against the child’s interests. While enhancing a child’s height or intellectual potential may not improve their life, it is unlikely to be any more damaging than myriads of other choices parents currently make for their children, from the music lessons they force on them, to their diet, to their schools.

In practice, certain limits would need to be placed on the types of genetic choices allowed, but social rather than legal means, acting both on the doctor and the parent, should minimize the more shady genetic meddling, like choosing hair or eye color, to prevent the commodification of children. This is not the domain for hard government regulation. Rather, these choices should be guided by how we understand the nature of the person, and it is in this respect that a discussion of enhancement in sports is timely.

Enhancement in Sports

On this issue, Sandel finally leaves abstract categories, and says we must consider this issue on purely functional grounds. As he says, the deciding criteria when considering the morality of enhancements in sports (whether chemical like steroids or physical like bionic limbs) is the purpose and ultimate goal of the sport. The legitimate enhancements ones are those that perfect rather than obscure the qualities and talents that the sport is meant to demonstrate – and is thus sport-dependent. Racket improvements in tennis or running shoes for runners (his example) do not interfere or obviate the participants’ skills but rather allow more fine-tuned performance. In no sense do they corrupt the sport. On the other hand, field and track athletes who are thus able to achieve unprecedented feats are distinctly less interesting. A shotputter on steroids is much like a drag race – perhaps an interesting show, but hardly a sport as such. The distinction is subjective but rooted in what we imagine to be the purpose of sports in general and a given sport in particular: exercise of skill, elegance, determination, endurance, etc.

Returning to the case of the parents, most crudely put, what is the purpose of children or particular characteristics for them? Or, rather, how do we think about character traits and other human qualities – to what extent do they impact on our self-image? Is musical ability just a ‘faculty’ (as Plato would put it) or is it part of our very self?

In Conclusion

So the moral outcomes rest on a fine distinction – are we adding characteristics – say mathematical talent – to a given child? Or are we creating a child to spec, like playing SimChild, with intelligence x, height y, language ability z? We have to think about the nature of self, how we construct our identity. The former primarily engages the eugenics question and I think only becomes problematic on the grand scale, while the latter is potentially subject to most of Sandel’s and Habermas’s objections… but how convincing are they?

On the one hand, the idea that parental participation in determining their children’s genes will have terrible effects on the child’s self-image (a la Habermas) blithely ignores the tremendous role parental influence in all its forms already plays in a child’s growth. Habermas in particular seems to be completely oblivious to the widely accepted role ‘nurture’ plays in the process, as if living in a 19th century pre-Freud world that imagines genetics to be uniquely indelible. On the other hand, now that we know genetic factors have similar influence to childhood environment, his insight might instead suggest that we should curb already existing parental influence through childhood rather than allowing that influence to extend into the child’s genetic make up.

My point here is that there are no a priori philosophically deducible answers to be had on this question for the individual. It is not morality which should guide us here but empirical psychological data which illuminates how the self-image and child-parent relationships are affected by the application of these new technologies. If we find that parents fundamentally view their children differently (for the worse) as a result, this would be a decisive argument against them. If nothing of the sort manifests itself, I argue we have no philosophical reason to hold back. Of course, the necessary experimental data may be difficult to obtain, but the point is that any limitation should be justified on practical, psychological grounds, not mere speculation; we’re dealing with a question of discipline competency, as it were. So, for one, in regard to Sandel’s point about commodification of children, as much as I agree that choice is at times harmful, so many other factors are to be considered that this effect may entirely disappear. And if I was in that position, I would push for the best damn genes money can buy.

8 comments:

Anonymous said...

I remember someone saying once: it is those relationships, events, people whom you don't choose that are the dearest...

Anonymous said...

Would you really engineer your child? And when they didn't become as intelligent as promised, would you be disappointed in them? You would create expectations that your child would have to live up to because you paid money for that to be true...and what if they didn't? I just think that there are so many factors to making a wonderful person that changing one or two genes makes no sense, what if the child is more kind than smart - does that make them less of a person? If we were allowed to engineer kids, like you said, everyone would adjust for the same characteristics which are considered good at the moment - one type of intelligence, height, whatever...that would be a sad world, that little something that makes people unique might disappear... I don't know, I suppose what I just said makes little sense. It certainly isn't a valid argument for anything.

It's just that when I think about people filling out a form ahead of time and getting a little custom made baby...I feel sad. And, I can't describe why or how. We do, as you said, have an awful lot of control as parents to mold children by nurture and we give them bits of our nature. But, it is the little surprises in who that child is that we learn to love. Will we really love as much something that we expect and will we not be disappointed when it doesn't quite work out our way? Maybe there should be research as you say...but after this research is done, it will be too late to stop "progress". Maybe I am that person who looks sadly at the last remnants of a green forest standing in a prime real estate location, knowing that it will be knocked down for some much "better" uses...

About another point, there are always borderline cases between prevention of diseases and pure out enhancement, borderline cases between what can be considered reconstructive plastic surgery and what is just for looks. Do those few borderlines mean that there is no distinction? Maybe I misinterpreted you...but it seems like you are saying that because the distinction is blurry and difficult, we should not be making it. I don't agree.

I am always a fan of looking at practical information instead of wild speculations. I also think that we do need to examine what comprises the nature of self - maybe that is the study we should pursue. Meanwhile, since we are unfortunately already heading in the direction of choosing children's sex, I would at least argue for slowing down this progress in order make sure that it is a controlled process. It needs to be regulated and limited, if only for the sake of seeing what happens first. Making children smarter isn't an emergency necessity, unlike trying to change whether a child is born with fatal physical deficiencies...it can wait for us to see if this is the right path for progress to follow and how it should flow...

Anonymous said...

One last point of concern for me is that when people do something for themselves, they rarely consider the outcome for society. In economic terms, they will not internalize all of the externalities their actions will cause. Imagine the inexpensive ability to choose the child's sex in china or india. The places where up until now little baby girls are being killed for being born a girl. What if most of the people of one generation chose what is the most desired sex, a boy? There would be a great imbalance of sexes with unpredictable outcomes in all sorts of social spheres, progress, and even future birth rates. That's just one example of not considering all of the externalities...there are many more. I am not fear-mongering, but only re-affirming that there need to be limits, definite limits and decisions made between engineering and correcting medical problems which could cause fatal or significant hardships to a child. I guess I've finally talked out my point of view. There it is...

Velikii Kombinator said...

The nostalgia you expect to feel when this technology spreads is not quite warranted because (at least the technology we imagine now) has relatively little impact on the child when they grow. Aside from simple things like height (I think), you're really just giving predispositions. There's plenty of room left for surprises. But the unsatisfied expectations you mention - that's a great point.

As far as distinction between prevention of disease and enhancement, i don't mean that because they are blurry they don't exist, but rather, they are harder to treat as moral rather than practical distinctions.

In regard to the social impact of individual decisions - yes, it is a danger. The case you mentioned in china or india already exists - they have a 1.3 and 1.4 ratio respectively, if I remember correctly. Regulation for cases like this is required - you are right, but I'm not sure how much you can generalize to genetic selection in general.

Joshua said...

If we find that parents fundamentally view their children differently (for the worse) as a result, this would be a decisive argument against them.

Just for clarification, would this really be an argument against the technologies? I would have thought this would be more of an argument against the parent's attitudes.

Take, for example, the attitude (mentioned in the above comments) that some Asian nations have towards female children. The fact that 50% (or so) of parents view girls differently (for the worse) than boys is not an argument against having (or choosing) girls. Rather, it is an argument against the sexist attitudes of the parents.

Would you really say "no, you can't choose to have a girl, because you don't respect the equality of the sexes"?

Velikii Kombinator said...

Joshua, you certainly make a good point, a clarification is in order. Clearly, attitudes should not always be taken as sacred and above question. I would say we should realize that some attitudes should be respected and viewed as having a moral weight, and others not. If the parents' attitude was simply one of dread of technology as such, say, we would probably think it is worth changing.

But I do think that there is a class of psychological responses by parents that we would see as undesirable, which would outweigh the arguments for the technology. Very tentatively, I would characterize this as a distinction between attitudes based on cultural norms (i.e. racism/sexism in the past) and ones rooted in more basic human psychology. I think the latter would count as a (morally?) relevant argument. A glance in a book on evolutionary psychology will reveal myriads of evolved attitudes which - even if we for whatever reason consider undesirable - are here to stay in our minds at least until we transhumanize :)

Anonymous said...

The sense of wonder in looking at a new born child would be lost once we start trying to create perfect children based on our choices.

Marks, awards, tests etc. would lose its value. Certainly we can't test genetically altered persons. In our desire to attain perfection, we are only going to wreck our future.

Vanessa @ Future of Engineering Blog
http://tinyurl.com/4njehj

Anonymous said...

perth copa characterize toothpaste saka cooperate terrain individually stella island hirwani
lolikneri havaqatsu